Assessing
the Foundations of Conscious Computing:
A
Bayesian Exercise
June 2001
Questions have long been posed with about whether we might one day be able to create computational systems that experience subjective states similar to those experienced by people. The challenge of understanding and explaining conscious experience extends well beyond discussions among philosophers. Many people, including AI scientists, pursuing principles of automated reasoning and decision making, and neurobiologists and psychologists, with interests in nervous systems and cognition, reflect about the nature of subjective states.
Given the absence of scientific methods for probing the principles and machinery of such conscious experience, beliefs about the nature and requirements of feeling and experiencing are diverse. When topics touching on consciousness, awareness, subjectivity, feeling and qualia arise in conversation, people are faced with a spectrum of beliefs about the foundations of subjective experience, and on related beliefs about the feasibility of one day developing computational algorithms and architectures that could achieve what we might call conscious computing. Such a diversity in beliefs appears extends to scientists with expertise in cognition, including decision scientists, cognitive psychology, neurobiology, and artificial intelligence.
To promote discussion, I’ve found it useful to assess the strength of belief that people have about different explanations for conscious experience. Rather than seek commitment to a single hypothesis, I find it valuable to take a Bayesian perspective on assessing beliefs under uncertainty. With such an approach, we lay out a set of distinct possibilities about the basis for conscious experience, engage people about clarifying and refining the hypotheses, and then assessing the likelihood of each hypothesis as being the true explanation. Such an assessment can be useful for revealing common patterns of belief and for focusing discussion.
The assessment of an explicit set of probabilities across a space of possibilities that provide conceptual coverage at a broad level of abstraction supports the admission of multiple possibilities with different degrees of belief, and helps to frame questions about the kinds of experiments, results, models, and observations that might be useful for updating the probabilities.
So, let’s formulate a set of broad possibilities, attempting to define a candidate space of mutually exclusive and exhaustive set of possibilities. We’ll work at a high-level of abstraction and talk about broad categories that could house more detailed hypotheses as further refinements. We’ll force the set of possibilities to be exhaustive by considering an explicit Other category, containing all possible explanations that don’t fit into one of the other broad hypotheses.
As an exercise, I’ll ask readers
to reflect about the probability that the correct explanation for conscious
experience lays within each hypothesis.
These assessed probabilities represent individuals’ beliefs about the
basis for consciousness, expressed as likelihoods of the ultimate truth of each
of the categories. One way to view such
probability assessments is to imagine that a clairvoyant who knows the actual
truth will soon reveal the nature of consciousness. The likelihoods represent the probabilities
of each hypothesis being the one pointed out as being the right explanation by
the clairvoyant.
Figure 1. Formulation of a space of hypotheses about subjective experience. After seeking agreement on the essence of each hypothesis, we can assess beliefs, in terms of the differing likelihoods of a mutually exclusive and exhaustive set of hypotheses.
Let us now explore a set of candidate hypotheses. Figure 1 captures a potential space of possible explanations for conscious experience. These definitions are meant to conjure up a “conceptual centroid,” capturing the essence of each explanation class. It’s clear that there is some potential difference of interpretation of the hypotheses, and so, to be more precise, people should have the opportunity during communications about beliefs to refine and personalize the definitions of the hypotheses and to introduce new categories of explanation. Let’s review each of a set of proposed hypotheses.
Theological Foundations includes the set of explanations that view conscious entities as having foundations in the spiritual world, outside of or in distinction to the mechanistic, scientific universe studied by physicists, chemists, and biologists. These explanations implicitly or explicitly pose conscious experience as arising as an essential property of souls or other experiencing entities founded on what one might refer to as classical theological or spiritual constructs, as captured, for example, by the notions of individuals in Buddhist, Christian, Islamic, Hindu, Jewish, and other organized religions.
Information Processing covers the set of hypotheses that consider subjective experience as
being generated by some aspect of information processing supported by a
computational system. As an example, the
hypothesis includes the assertion that subjective experience is created by, or
associated with, patterns of coordinated information processing that support
the real-time capabilities for sensory integration, reasoning, and action
demonstrated by the human nervous system. People with strong beliefs
about the Information Processing hypothesis tend to believe that
conscious experience is based on some form of algorithmic activity, whether
that form of algorithmic activity is performed by cell-based nervous activity,
a set of silicon memory units and gates, a universal Turing machine, or a
contraption built from Styrofoam balls, wood sticks, and rubber bands.
Mysterious Fabric spans the set of hypotheses that explain consciousness as hinging
critically on some as yet poorly understand property or properties of the
physical universe that was discovered and leveraged through evolutionary
processes. The essential nature of the property and its role in subjective
experience may one day be revealed via ongoing efforts in physics and
neurobiology. Such a property may be
metaphorically or in reality related to some fundamental aspect of quantum
physics, or another property of energy, matter in space time.
Other refers
to the set of all explanations that are not captured by the explicitly defined
categories. That is, we ask people to assess the likelihood that “something
else is going on,” significantly distinct from the other, explicit
categories. Other includes
explanations that fall outside of the explicit hypotheses, include explanations
that represent reformulations, extensions, or combinations of the definitions
of the explicit categories—given personal interpretations of the definitions of
the explicit hypotheses.
Notice that we can
refine the hypotheses space, by breaking out as distinct hypotheses, more
precise, finer-grained explanations. For
example, as portrayed in Figure 2, we refine Information Processing into
IP-Competency and IP-Leap.
Figure 2. Refinement
of the space of hypotheses. In this case, we refine Information Processing
into the IP Leap and IP Competency classes
IP-Competency is a refinement of Information Processing
that explains conscious experience as being based in information processing,
and asserts that such subjective states are an unavoidable aspect of increasing
cognitive competency. That is, what we
call consciousness is unavoidable as real-time sensory integration and
information processing become increasingly competent. From
the point of view of IP-Competency, searching for a special word or
concept like consciousness is chasing an illusory “distinct” notion. Our
self awareness and subjective experience is simply the way entities with our
abilities necessarily must feel. Should
an explanation in the IP-Competency category be true, there would be
nothing explicit to discover about conscious experience with the increasing
competency of reasoning systems
IP-Leap is a refinement of Information Processing that asserts that subjective experience is based on special, potentially interesting and surprising information processing. IP-Leap explanations assert that conscious experience is the result of some interesting novel information-processing analysis, coordination, integration, architecture, etc., that endows nervous systems with valuable capabilities that would not necessarily be obtainable or obtainable with the same overall architecture or resource limitations without such special processing or machinery. IP-Leap explanations suggest that there are some discoverable analytical and/or architectural aspects of cognitive systems that would enhance our insights about understanding and potentially synthesizing systems capable of supporting conscious experiences.
In performing assessment, we can identify different patterns of belief among the population. Figures 3 through 5 capture several classes of belief about the foundations for subjective experience.
Figure 3 captures the beliefs of an individual who finds consciousness mysterious, with an assessment that the explanation is likely founded on some as yet poorly understood property of the universe. I have found that many people with strong beliefs that consciousness likely is linked to some, as yet poorly understood, essential property of the physical universe, often cite an explanation that has “something to do with quantum physics.” In this case, a person asserts that the next most likely hypothesis is Other, or something outside of the explicit hypotheses, followed by IP Leap hypothesis, and then IP Competency, followed last by Theology.
Figure 3. A pattern of belief with weight on Mysterious Fabric hypotheses.
Figure 4. A pattern of belief with weight on the Information-Processing hypotheses, with a leaning toward IP Leap.
Figure 4 captures a pattern of beliefs leaning towards the conscious experience as a very special kind of information processing, followed by some probability that something else is going on, with an even less likelihood that the subjective world is an inescapable aspect of the intellectual competency associated with human (and potentially other) nervous systems. Although this person gives some probability to the Mysterious Fabric hypothesis, only a small probability is assigned to theological hypotheses.
Figure 5. A pattern of belief with weight on hypotheses in the Theological Foundations category.
Figure 5 represents beliefs of a person with heaviest weight on the probability that subjective experience is founded in theology. Although, the person has assigned the highest probability to the Theological Foundations hypothesis, significant belief is also assigned to the Mysterious Fabric hypothesis, and to the Other category, expressing the probability that the explanation for conscious experience is rooted in a hypothesis outside of those expressed in Figure 2. This person largely rejects the Information Processing hypotheses.
Some readers may find that the categories of explanation do not cover the space of possibilities in a satisfying way. They may wish to modify the categories presented and recommend reformulating the categories or introducing new candidate explanations. Working to define a revised set of mutually exclusive and exhaustive categories can be a useful exercise.
What are your own beliefs about the foundations of our conscious experience? How would you apportion probabilities that each of the distinct explanations mentioned above (or a set of hypotheses of your own) above is the correct one? As we mentioned above, one approach to assessing the probabilities is to imagine that you encounter an omniscient clairvoyant who knows the truth about consciousness. For each category of explanation under consideration, assess the probability that the clairvoyant will soon tell you that the category is the correct explanation.
Here is a link to a tool created to enable readers to assess the probabilities of the hypotheses discussed. You have the option of sharing these assessments as part of a survey that aggregates the information into summaries of the probabilities that people assign to different explanations for conscious experience.
Access pdf version of essay.